|
The
Betrayal of Democracy: Exclusion of the Common Man
in Herman Melville’s “Bartleby,
the Scrivener”
by Pamela Prochaska
George Edward Woodberry, author of the
Heart
of Man, published in 1899, emphasized the significance of the role
of the individual as an active and equal partner in American democratic
rule: “ The doctrine of the equality of mankind by virtue of their birth
as men, with its consequent right to equality of opportunity for self-development
as a part of social justice, establishes a common basis of conviction,
in respect to man, and a definite end as one main object of the State;
and these elements are primary in the democratic scheme. Liberty
is the next step, and is the means by which that end is secured.
It is so cardinal in democracy …” to strive for a balance between the individual
and the mass, so that the identification of the common man as an American
ensures him of the promises proposed by the government. (226-227).
During the early 1800’s, America struggled
with the search for identity and the shift toward Liberal Individualism.
The revolutionary words of freedom, equality, and brotherhood gave birth
to the doctrine of government by the people, for the people, and of the
people. These principles were the substance of democracy; these tenets,
though fundamentally sound and idealistically honorable, seemed elementary,
but to assume that the ideals of democracy were rudimentary and easily
attained was a national betrayal. This betrayal, depicted as the
futility of the individual to achieve political and representational inclusion
in the government and, more importantly, the realization of his importance,
belied the struggle.
The shift toward Liberal Individualism
created the need for a balance between the individual and the community.
The election of 1828, which propelled Andrew Jackson to national prominence,
marked the emergence of the voice of the common man; “democracy lay ahead,
while a traditional concept of stately honor was unwilling to yield to
it” (Burstein 195). This unwillingness to alter national traditions
was evident in the struggle between the individual and the community.
However, with the emphasis now on the advancement of the individual, many
citizens wondered how the new country would maintain the national community.
In an attempt to address this struggle, Romantic writers such as Melville
concerned themselves with an escape from the traditions and the authorities
of the past. In promoting the formation of a unique American Literature
with a unique national identity, the Romantics created the interplay between
the reader and the writer and, in doing so, stressed the importance of
the interdependence between the individual and the community. Romantic
authors critically studied the social values of the emerging democratic
nation in order to create a new identity rather than a representation.
Hawthorne and Melville defined the Romance genre as the self-conscious
expression of nineteenth-century America: “ a common vision of our literature
as distinguished from an English literary tradition. Ironically,
the most striking feature of their vision was its kinship” with the emerging
voice of the individual. (Strout 1)
Herman Melville depicts the struggle for
individual sovereignty in his short story “Bartleby the Scrivener”; through
the actions and the attitudes of the elite narrator in the story, the deceptiveness
of democracy is evident. The ideology of democracy purports that
all men are created equal and are equally represented in the voice of government.
Yet, the scriveners as common men are separated from the elite narrator
who creates the walls of exclusion in order to perpetuate the myth of his
individual importance. In “Bartleby, the Scrivener”, Melville demonstrates
that, in reality, the implementation of American democracy in the 1830’s
– 1850’s excludes the individual and, in doing so, fails to achieve a balance
between the individual and the community.
In the opening of the tale, the narrator
perceives himself as a man of conviction but, in reality, his life, a meaningless
existence, lacks creativity and uniqueness. The lawyer offers his philosophy
of life: “I am a man who, from his youth upwards, has been filled with
a profound conviction that the easiest way of life is the best” (2403).
The lawyer is a man of assumptions; he assumes that his comfortable life,
free from the economic hardships that plague the scriveners, mirrors their
lives. For thirty years, he manages the fortunes of elite members
of society; accustomed to the certainty of his profession, the lawyer enjoys
that “snug berth in the safe business of manipulating other people’s money”
(Hans 286). However, the lawyer enjoys his association only with
those defined by their wealth and, more importantly, defines himself because
of his advantaged position. But in the revelation of his self-definition
as the “drawer-up of recondite documents of all sorts” (2407), the lawyer
echoes the meaninglessness of reality: he merely copies the work of other
men; he creates nothing new or unique. Alienated from his wealthy
benefactors, he mimics the impotence of an aimless profession. In
their book Federalists Reconsidered, authors Ben-Atar and Oberg,
justify the quest of the narrator: “For men of great dignity and
consideration …to prefer private [good] to public good, the honors, wealth,
and pleasure of time, to those of eternity, [is] inconsistent with the
reason and dignity of man” (205).
Ignoring the plight of the scriveners who
suffer from despair and economic hardship, the narrator establishes his
economic superiority and applauds his insight into their lives. The
lawyer considers himself a man of status as the Master of the Chancery,
he believes that he understands the oppressive lives of his scriveners:
“The Nature of my avocations for the last thirty years has brought me more
than ordinary contact with … an interesting and somewhat singular set of
men … the law-copyists or scriveners … I have known very many of them,
professionally and privately, and if I pleased, could relate divers histories,
at which good-natured gentlemen might smile, and sentimental souls might
weep” (2402). Therein lies the assumption of power by the lawyer;
he believes that he knows the lives of the scriveners simply because of
his lengthy business association with them. But in reality, his association
with them is a vacuous relationship. As the lawyer reveals his knowledge
about each copyist, he assigns each one a certain value. Bainard
Cowan, author of “Melville’s soul’s code,” identifies the origin of this
value that is placed on the individual as the “notion of idealistic individualism
– which seeks to locate a culture’s meaningful values within the individual”
(639). But the description of each scrivener only reaffirms the narrator’s
opinion of the men: he tolerates them for his own benefit and his own advancement.
The narrator introduces the scriveners: “ … I had two
persons as copyists in my employment,
and a promising lad as an office boy. First, Turkey; second, Nippers;
third, Ginger Nut. These may seem names, the like of which are not
usually found in the Directory. In truth, they were nicknames … and
deemed expressive of their respective persons or characters” (2402).
The scriveners, all victims of humanity, suffer the loss of identity; they
are nameless. Seen but rarely heard, the persona of each reflects
the flaws enumerated by the lawyer. “Turkey was a short, pursy, Englishman
… my own age … [who] displayed his fullest beams from his red and radiant
countenance … he was apt to be altogether too energetic … not only would
he be reckless … [he] was rather noisy … Nevertheless … he was … a most
valuable person to me” (2404). Turkey is a short, portly, elderly
gentleman; he suffers from hypertension and diabetes, two diseases that
often befall the elderly. Unable to concentrate on his work, Turkey suffers
from tremors because of his elevated blood glucose. The narrator tolerates
the copyist’s habits with indifference. In the afternoons, the narrator
distances himself from the scrivener; his neglect reaffirms the idea that
Sean Wilentz purports in his article “Striving for Democracy:” that all
history had been a battle between the few and the many …” enabling America
to be built by “a country of self-made men …” (50-51). The lawyer,
a self-made man, reaffirms his position at the expense of the copyists.
Although he suffers from illnesses from
deplorable working conditions, the second scrivener, Nippers, displays
a generosity that is misunderstood by the narrator. Suffering from alcoholism,
poverty, and indigestion and described by the lawyer as a temperate young
fellow, Nippers displays “an irritable, brandy-like disposition” (2406).
The narrator surmises that ambition causes Nippers to suffer from indigestion.
In reality, he works on a desk that is unsuitable for the tedium of a copyist:
“he put chips under it, blocks of various sorts, bits of pasteboard … if,
for the sake of easing his back, he brought the table lid at a sharp angle
well up towards his chin … then he declared that it stopped the circulation
in his arms … In short, the truth of the matter was, Nippers knew not what
he wanted” (2405). Again, the lawyer deems himself the omniscient
soul of his employees. He describes Nippers as a plunderer when,
in reality, the scrivener suffers from inhumane and unsuitable working
conditions. The physical and psychological pain that these conditions
incur causes him to be irritable; the long hours of tedious work with no
hope for advancement or ease frustrates the scrivener. Nippers suffers
from ill health like Turkey. And like Turkey, he has no escape from
the condition of his life. Extending generosity toward his fellow
man, Nippers serves as a ward-politician, collecting overdue debts.
Crediting Nippers “diseased ambition” among his many faults, the narrator
fails to see the soul in need; instead he praises himself as “an eminently
safe man … my first grand point to prudence; my next, method” (2403).
Perceiving the humanitarian work which Nippers performs as a lawyer for
the poor as a failure of character the lawyer fails to realize the generous
nature of his scrivener. The lawyer prefers the safety and prudence
of his prestigious law office, where the walls obscure the truth of poverty
and destitution of the common man, and the realm of an illusory existence
appeases him.
Without the concern of the narrator, Ginger-Nut
is relegated to a life of poverty and destined to hopelessness. Ginger-Nut
is the narrator’s third employee: “sent … to my office as [a] student
at law, errand boy, and cleaner and sweeper, at the rate of one dollar
a week. He had a little desk to himself, but he did not use it very
much. Upon inspection, the drawer exhibited … various sorts of nuts”
(2406). The narrator assumes that Ginger-Nut is interested not in law but
in fulfilling his role as errand boy for the scriveners, but the child
is caught in a cycle of poverty: hungry, bored and forlorn. Although the
narrator perceives the child’s circumstances as serious, he fails to help
him; the lawyer neither feeds the child nor apprentices him in preparation
for a better life. Described as “proverbially a dry, husky sort of
business” (2407), the narrator concludes that the law profession is ill
suited for the child. As a favor to the young boy’s father who is
“ambitious of seeing his son on the bench instead of a cart” (2406), the
narrator controls the future of the child; he perceives his humanitarian
effort of employing the child as noble but fails to apprentice him.
He justifies his neglect of the boy because “[to] this quick-witted youth
the whole noble science of the law was contained in a nutshell” (2406).
Again, as the omniscient predictor of the child’s ability to fulfill the
duties of a lawyer, the narrator negates the boy’s chances for a more prosperous
and fulfilled life; in his regard of the scriveners as men of meager worth,
the narrator merely fulfills his obligation.
The narrator disregards the needs of his
struggling scriveners and confines them to impoverished lives without
hope for advancement. The existence of the lawyer is fraught with illusion
and disdain for the employees of his office; he tolerates their weaknesses
in order to confirm his importance. In his book The Irony of Democracy:
An Uncommon Introduction to American Politics, Thomas R. Dye asserts
that “life in a democracy … is shaped by a handful of men.
An elite is the few who have power; the masses are the many who do not
… Being more influential, they [the elites] are privileged; and being privileged,
they have, with few exceptions, a special stake in the continuation of
the system in which their privileges rest” (3). Thus the lawyer perpetuates
the status of the common men as unable to transcend their life of poverty
and hardship; he reinforces the restraints that limit their success which
ensures their inability to transcend their lives of poverty and despair.
The addition of Bartleby as a passive and
reliable scrivener maintains the equilibrium of the law office. The passive
nature of Bartleby’s character pleases the lawyer; described as “a man
of so singularly sedate an aspect …” (2407), the narrator engages Bartleby
as a scrivener who is easily led and comfortably controlled. Hired
to transcribe and mimic the words that merely represent the ideas and efforts
of others, Bartleby offers the narrator a stability that the office needs.
Furthermore, Bartleby “operate [s] beneficially upon the flighty temper
of Turkey, and the fiery one of Nippers” (2407). In order to maintain
homeostasis in the workplace, the four law clerks work together to continue
the narrator’s life of ease. Douglas M. Strong, author of Perfectionist
Politics, reaffirms the determination of the narrator as ego-centric:
“ By failing to sustain their principles for very long, they [the elite
narrator] demonstrated how difficult it is for personal freedom and social
order to function simultaneously with an increasingly diverse democratic
society” (167). Therefore, the narrator must carefully control the
scriveners. Although a diverse group, the law clerks, led by Bartleby,
maintain the social order of the law office under the guiding direction
of the narrator.
Bartleby’s mechanical work demonstrates
the futility of his life, an existence without hope or advancement.
“At first Bartleby did an extraordinary quantity of writing … he seemed
to gorge himself on my documents” (2407) explains the narrator. An industrious
and diligent copyist, Bartleby seems willing to accommodate the narrator
by copying volumes of law papers. But Bartleby displays no joy in
his work, as the lawyer observes that the law clerk writes for hours “silently,
palely, and mechanically” (2407). Caught in the pointless employment
as an automaton, Bartleby has no reason to be cheerful; his endless hours
of work merely accommodate the advantaged life of the narrator.
Bartleby’s isolation in the office, through
his confinement within the walls, exacerbates the disparity between himself
and the elite narrator. In the placement of his desk next to a wall,
Bartleby is limited in his movements; new buildings built adjacent to the
tiny window obscure the limited view and “commanded at present no view
at all” (2407). The confinement behind the walls destroys any glimmer
of hope for Bartleby; his limitation of movement and thought incarcerate
him in a prison of doom. Melville writes that Bartleby’s vision is
so narrowed that it offers no window of opportunity, no hope for the future:
“within three feet of the [window] panes was a wall, and the light came
down from far above … as from a very small opening in a dome” (2407). Relegated
to the least hopeful and most depressing conditions of existence, Bartleby
is never free from his confinement. Alienated from other human beings,
sequestered from the inspiration of light, and denied the possibility of
advancement or a better life, he suffers from internal and external impotence;
the walls that separate the scrivener and the lawyer “destroy the universality
and immortality of being” (Stovall 68).
Trapped within a pointless existence, Bartleby
refuses to verify his work and disrupts the social order of the law office;
thus the emergence of the his voice disarms the complacency of the narrator.
The lawyer assigns little value or importance to the presence of Bartleby
in his office and to the tasks that he accomplishes. In referring
to his task as “trifling” (2407), the narrator reaffirms his ambivalence
toward the plight of the scrivener until Bartleby asserts his preference
not to review the law documents. “Now and then, in the haste of business
… was to avail myself of his [Bartleby’s] services on such trivial occasions
… Imagine my surprise, nay, my consternation, when … Bartleby in a singular
mild, firm voice, replied ‘I would prefer not to’”(2408). Bartleby
asserts his own individuality, his personal power of choice: he asserts
his will of non-compliance. As the representative of the common man,
he breaks free of the constraints held in place by the narrator.
Despite the risks, Bartleby abandons the safety net of complicity and dares
to assert his will. In the confrontation of will, the common scrivener
releases the repression that binds him to a life of trivial tasks, a life
of meaningless toil and suffering. Now he has a choice and demands
to be heard. In the repetition of his reply: “ I prefer not to”,
Bartleby defines himself as an uncommon man, one who is willing to resist
the authority and assert himself against a culture that “is biased in favor
of individual desires over social needs, private interests over public
interest, and individual liberty over community” (Hudson 109).
Hesitant to release Bartleby from his duties
as a copyist, the lawyer maintains his reputation in the community and
perpetuates his own self-interest. The narrator rationalizes the behavior
of the scrivener: “it is seldom the case when a man is browbeaten in some
unprecedented and violently unreasonable way, he begins to stagger in his
own plainest faith. He begins … to surmise that … all the justice
and all the reason is on the other side” (2409). Unable to recognize
the plight of the life of the common scrivener as intolerable, the narrator
justifies Bartleby’s non-conformity as a flaw of reason. The narrator,
believing himself the victim of reprehensible behavior by his scrivener,
reaffirms his own good nature: “Nothing so aggravates an earnest person
as a passive resistance … I regarded Bartleby and his ways. Poor
fellow! Thought I … his eccentricities are involuntary. To befriend
Bartleby … will cost me nothing, while I lay up in my soul what will eventually
prove a sweet morsel for my conscience” (2410). Hancock concludes
that the chasm between the advantaged and the common man is so extended
that it separates the common man “from the influences of another, a democratic
man has no access to the things themselves, because to know things, a person
has to go outside himself …” (215). But the lawyer refuses
to look beyond his own self-interest; instead, he justifies the reason
that he keeps Bartleby in his employment: his reputation will suffer if
he fires the indigent copyist. The narrator rationalizes his efforts as
just and righteous and his interaction with the scrivener as fair.
But Andrew W. Achenbaum, author of the article, “The social compact in
American history,” asserts that the assurance of equality among men is
tenuous “when the condition of society becomes democratic and men adopt
as a general principle that it is good and lawful to judge of all things
for oneself” (16). In that singular perception of inequality, the
common man discovers the absence of fraternity and resolves himself to
abandon the search for the bond of brotherhood.
Frustrated with Bartleby’s self-assertion
and preference, the narrator confronts the scrivener’s defiance of authority.
By the assertion of his individuality, Bartleby’s behavior is perplexing
to the narrator: “ I resolved upon this; - I would … give him a twenty
dollar bill over and above whatever I might owe him, and tell him his services
were no longer required …The time has come; you must quit the place; I
am sorry for you; here is money; but you must go” (2415-2417). Because
Bartleby is so forlorn, the lawyer pities him. Yet, his pity quickly
turns to repulsion when Bartleby asserts his individuality and states that
he prefers not to leave the office; compliance with Bartleby’s wish to
remain in the office creates fear in the mind of the narrator. Unaccustomed
to Bartleby’s assertiveness and experiencing a sense of vulnerability himself,
the lawyer demands Bartleby to leave. Deciding the fate of the common scrivener
empowers the lawyer and consequently, he denies the shame of his own existence.
“He must project it [his shame] onto another individual in order to distance
himself from the repulsive origins he has found to be the defining core
of his desolate being” (Hans 289).
Unable to evict Bartleby from his law office
and, more importantly, from his life, the narrator seeks refuge from him,
thus the radical individualism of the narrator violates the democratic
principles of consideration promised to all men. Seeking refuge from
the reality of the scrivener’s plight and frustrated by his lack of control
over Bartleby, the narrator escapes from his office: “ Since he will not
quit me, I must quit him … I will move elsewhere … and shall no longer
require … [Bartleby’s] services” (2422). Moving his practice
to another building is the last resort for the lawyer. He surmises that
there is no other solution to rid himself of the memory of Bartleby.
Unconcerned that Bartleby is homeless and impoverished the narrator rejects
the needs of the scrivener and excludes him as a valuable member of the
community of man. William E. Hudson, author of American Democracy
in Peril, asserts that the inclusion of the common man is challenged
by American individualism: “Most fundamentally, it [American individualism]
erodes the habits of the heart that tie democratic citizens to one another
and promote civic virtue” (108). In this way, the lawyer imposes
the restraints of his self-serving individualism on Bartleby, who as a
common man, is imprisoned within a system of futility and excluded from
the promises of democracy: equality, freedom, and brotherhood. Matthew
Arnold reaffirms the encumbrances of Liberal Individualism in his book,
Discourses in America, written in 1885. He compares the individual,
“the working part of the community … not much better off than slaves, and
not more seriously regarded … the mass to be considered has not leisure,
but is bound, for its own great good, and for the great good of the world
at large, to plain labour … dissatified with these pursuits and unfitted
for them” (77) as victims of a democratic society.
Overwhelmed by the feelings of rejection,
Bartleby succumbs to abandonment by the narrator. The narrator is notified
that Bartleby is relocated to the Tombs. On a visit to the jail, the narrator
searches for Bartleby. Immured in the silent tomb where hopeless
men are surrounded by thick walls that protect them from the harsh world,
Bartleby lies “strangely huddled at the base of the wall, his knees drawn
up, and lying on his side, his head touching the cold stones, [there]
I saw the wasted Bartleby. But nothing stirred” (2427). Bartleby
dies the same way that he lived: alone, isolated from the external world,
relegated to an existence outside the bond of brotherhood, and rejected
by the very men
who profess to care for those in need.
Without a reason to live and lost in the relentless pursuit of inclusion
for all men, he lies at the base of the walls that protect him from such
men. Having grown accustomed to the familiarity of confinement, the
walls reassure him in death; lying in the fetal position, Bartleby mocks
his birth and questions the purpose of a life filled with dejection and
hopelessness. “ Bartleby’s solitude preserves what self he has, yet
the cost of this preservation is his life” (Hans 287).
Herman Melville addresses the futile plight
of the individual in his short story “Bartleby, the Scrivener”. As
America endeavored to achieve a balance between the individual and the
community, Bartleby, a common man, is excluded from the promises of democracy.
Confined by those who erect walls of constraints, restrained by those who
protect the advantages that they uphold as theirs alone, and betrayed by
those he served, Bartleby is unable to transcend his life of hardship and
despair. His effort to assert his individuality, his self-will, is noble
and admirable, yet Melville concludes that his attempt was to no avail.
Melville recognizes the importance and worth of the common man as an integral
member of a democracy. Yet, he purports that society is merely a
collection of isolated individuals unable to perceive that the humanity
that exists outside the individual is important and worthy of the fulfillment
of the democratic promise. Thus, Melville reveals that equality and
freedom are relegated to only a few men who betray the ideals of a democratic
brotherhood in search of individual glory.
Works Cited
Achenbaum, W. Andrew. “The social compact
in American history.” Generations 22 (Winter 98-99): 15-18.
Arnold, Matthew. Discourses In America.
London: MacMillan, 1885.
Ben-Atar, Doron and Barbara B. Oberg. Federalists
Reconsidered. Charlottesville: UP Virginia, 1998.
Burstein, Andrew. Sentimental Democracy:
The Evolution of America’s Romantic Self-Image. New York: Hill and
Wang, 1999.
Cowan, Bainard. “Melville’s Soul Code.”
The
Southern Review 33 (Summer 1997): 637-41).
Dye, Thomas R. and L. Harmon Zeigler. The
Irony of Democracy. Belmont: Wadsworth, 1970.
Hancock, Ralph C. “Tocqueville’s practical
reason.” Perspectives on Political Science 27 (Fall 1998): 212-19.
Hans, James S. “Emptiness and plenitude
in Bartleby the scrivener and The crying of lot 49.” Essays in Literature
22 (Fall 1995): 285-99.
Hudson, William E. American Democracy
in Peril. Chatham: Chatham House, 1995.
Stovall, Floyd. American Idealism.
Port Washington: Kennikat, 1943.
Strong, Douglas M. Perfectionist Politics:
Abolitionism and The Religious Tensions Of American Democracy. Syracuse:
Syracuse UP, 1999.
Strout, Cushing. Making American Tradition.
New Brunswick: Rutgers UP, 1990.
Wilentz, Sean. “Striving for Democracy.”
The
Wilson Quarterly 23 (Spring 1999): 47-54.
Woodberry, George Edward. Heart of Man.
London: Macmillan, 1899.
Return to Top.
Return
to Index Page.
|